Top-Rated Free Essay
Preview

Hobbes VS. Locke VS. Rousseau

Powerful Essays
10874 Words
Grammar
Grammar
Plagiarism
Plagiarism
Writing
Writing
Score
Score
Hobbes VS. Locke VS. Rousseau
Hobbes vs. Locke vs. Rousseau/ State of Nature/ Allam/ 2013

“I am at the point of believing, that my labor will be as useless as the commonwealth of Plato. For Plato, also is of the opinion that it is impossible for the disorders of the state ever to be taken away until sovereigns be philosophers . . . I recover some hope that one time or other this writing of mine may fall into the hands of a sovereign who will consider it for himself, for it is short, and I think clear.”
-The Monster of Malmesbury (Thomas Hobbes), Leviathan1

Thomas Hobbes was born at Westport near Malmesbury in Wiltshire, England.2 A wealthy uncle paid for his education and sent him to Magdalen Hall, Oxford.3 Hobbes lived at a time of immense intellectual excitement, and the universities of his day were far from being at the cutting-edge of intellectual advance.4 The Oxford curriculum still consisted largely of scholastic logic and metaphysics, which he regarded as sterile pedantry and for which he had nothing good to say.5 Leaving university with a degree in scholastic logic and, it has been said, several more degrees of contempt for Aristotle in particular, and universities in general, Hobbes obtained a post as tutor to the Earl of Devonshire.6 He travelled widely with the Duke, moving in increasingly aristocratic circles and even meeting the celebrated Italian astronomer Galileo, in 1636.7 Hobbes also met another important figure, Sir Francis Bacon. Francis Bacon was a philosopher who rejected the Aristotelian logic and system, which basically was a speculative system, started out from some major assumptions and through deductions developed his philosophical system.8 Thomas Hobbes has a more cynical and realistic, view of human nature than the Greeks.9 Whilst he agrees that people have regard for their self-interest, there is little else Hobbes will accept from the ancients.10 Hobbes was considered by many of his contemporaries to be, if not actually an atheist, certainly a heretic.11 Indeed, after the Great Plague of 1666, in which 60,000 Londoners died, and the Great Fire straight afterwards, a parliamentary committee was set up to investigate whether heresy might have contributed to the two disasters.12 The list of possible causes includes Hobbes’ writings.13
Hobbes’ books are a strange mixture of jurisprudence, religious enthusiasm, and political iconoclasm.14 Hobbes’ political theory, then is that of someone who experienced both the English Civil War and the Scientific Revolution of the seventeenth century.15 This fact is important to our understanding of it.16 He formulated his political ideas several times, but it is in Leviathan that they find their most complete and influential statement.17 His approach to politics is self-consciously scientific.18 His technique of enquiry is delivered partly from the ‘resolutive-compositive’ method associated with Galileo and Bacon, and partly from the deductive reasoning that had so impressed him in Euclid.19 If we are to arrive at a sound understanding of politics, we must first analyze or resolve social wholes into their smallest component parts: namely, individual human beings.20 Then, having studied the properties and behavior of those parts in isolation, we can deduce from them, as it were from first principles, rational conclusions about social and political organization.21 He breaks down (by analysis) social phenomena into their basic constituents, and only then synthesizes these to produce a new theory.22 It is this technique, as much as his theory of power as the motivating spring of mankind, that makes Hobbes a distinctly modern thinker.23 His materialism is central to his account of human behavior.24 The body of each human being is, he thinks, only a complex mechanism, somewhat like a clock.25 Hobbes has a mechanistic Weltanschauung. We are bodies in constant motion.26 He seems in other words, to have a kind of materialistic psychology in which human behavior exhibits the same, as it were, mechanical tendencies as billiard balls that can be understood as obeying, again, geometric or causal processes of cause and effect.27
Before we proceed to his account of the state of nature, we will explore first some of his important ideas. First, is his skeptical view of knowledge. Hobbes was obsessed with the question about what can I know or, maybe put a different way, what am I entitled to believe, and there are many passages in Leviathan that testify to Hobbes’ fundamentally skeptical view of knowledge.28 He is a skeptic not because he believes that we can have no foundations for our beliefs, but he is skeptic in the sense that there can be no, on his view, transcendent of nonhuman foundations for our beliefs.29 We cannot be certain, he thinks, of the ultimate foundations of our knowledge and this explains you may have wondered about this, this explains the importance he attributes to such things as naming and attaching correct definitions to things.30 Knowledge, in other words, is for Hobbes a human construction and it is always subject to what human beings can be made to agree upon and that skeptical view of knowledge or at least skeptical view of the foundation of knowledge has far reaching consequences for him.31 This argument of Hobbes resembles the thesis of Berger and Luckmann’s book. The ongoing process of objectivation-externalization-internalization to construct, reconstruct, and deconstruct the world. In other words, knowledge and human reality is ‘socially constructed’.32 If all knowledge, according to Hobbes, ultimately rests on agreement about shared terms, he infers from that our reason, our rationality, has no share in what Plato or Aristotle would have called the divine Noos, the divine intelligence.33 Our reason does not testify to some kind of inner voice of conscience or anything that would purport to give it some kind of indubitable foundation.34 Such certainty as we have about anything is for Hobbes always provisional, discovered on the basis of experience and subject to continual revision in the light of further experience, and that again experiential conception of knowledge.35
Next, is his idea of the laws of nature. Fear is the basis, even of what Hobbes called the various laws of nature.36 The laws of nature for Hobbes are described as a precept or a general rule of reason that every man ought to endeavor peace and it is out of fear that we begin to reason and see the advantages of society; reason is dependent upon the passions, upon fear.37 The natural laws for Hobbes are not divine commands or ordinances, he says, but they are rules of practical reason figured out by us as the optimal means of securing our well-being.38 Ignorance of the law of nature is no excuse.39 According to Prof. Bacale-Ocampo LlB, there are two doctrines of the natural law: everyone must seek peace and follow it, and man being able, if others were too.40 Hobbes also said that there can be no unjust laws. There are two reasons for this proposition, according to Prof. Bacale-Ocampo LlB: law precedes justice, and the sovereign is the embodiment of all the people’s rights.41 This argument justifies Hobbes’ defense of the absolute and authoritarian power of his sovereign. The power of the sovereign, Hobbes continually insists, must be unlimited.42 This notion also resembles Art. XVI, Sec. III of the 1987 Philippine Constitution, that, “The State may not be sued without its consent.” In a very real sense, a suit against the State by its citizens is, in effect, a suit against the rest of the people represented by their common government – an anomalous and absurd situation indeed.43
Now, let’s go to his notion of the state of nature. The state of nature, a shocking phrase calculated to arouse the wrath of the Church, directly conflicting with the rosy biblical image of Adam and Eve in the Garden of Eden before the Fall.44 Hobbes thinks the ‘human machine’ is programmed to direct its energies selfishly.45 He doubts if it is ever possible for human beings to act altruistically, and even apparently benevolent action is actually self-serving, perhaps an attempt to make them feel good about themselves.46 Hobbes tells us, “. . . in the first place, I put for a general inclination of all mankind, a perpetual and restless desire of Power after Power, that ceaseth only in Death.”47 The desire for power is the cause of human strife and conflict.48 Finally, Hobbes most quoted statement, that in the state of nature, “. . . there is no place for Industry; because the fruit thereof is uncertain: and consequently no Culture of the Earth; no Navigation, nor use of the Commodities that may be imported by Sea; no Commodious Building; no instruments of moving, and removing such things as require much force; no knowledge of the face of the Earth; no account of Time; no Arts; no Letters; no Society; and which is worst of all, continual fear, and danger of violent death; And the life of man, solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.”49 The state of nature is simply a kind of condition of maximum insecurity.50 Hobbes continues, “Hereby it is manifest, that during the time men live without a common power to keep them all in awe, they are in that condition which is called War; and such a War, as is of every man against every man . . . the nature of war, consisteth not in actual fighting; but in the known disposition thereto, during all the time there is no assurance to the contrary.”51
There are three principle causes of quarrel. The first is competition, for gain; the second is diffidence and a compulsion for safety; whilst the final one is the compulsion for glory, and for reputation.52 Yet they all precipitate violence.53 Hobbes tells us, “The first use violence, to make themselves Masters of other men’s persons, wives, children, and cattle; the second, to defend them; the third, for trifles, as a word, a smile, a different opinion, and any other sign of undervalue either direct in their Persons, or by reflection in their Kindred, their Friends, their Nation, their Profession, or their Name.”54 Hobbes also asks the readers, “Let him, the reader, therefore ask himself, when taking a journey he arms himself and seeks to go well accompanied. When going to sleep, he locks his doors even when in his house, and even when in his house he locks his chest and this, when he know, he says, there be laws and public officers armed to avenge all injuries shall be done to him . . . Does he not therefore as much accuse mankind by his action as I do by my words?”55
In short, the members of the Hobbesian state of nature employs the classic prisoner’s dilemma. The strategic interests of the two individuals are antithetical to each other, and that keeps them from forming a social solidarity that would be best for them altogether.56 The prisoner’s dilemma is analogous to a social world in which public goods would be quite valuable to have, but in which individuals would lose something from contributing to the public good as long as other people do not.57 There has to be an assurance that the other side will live up to the bargain; but there is no way of knowing that, and in fact one can figure out that other people will act just like oneself.58 Whether one assumes that the other person is ultimately selfish, or merely distrusting, the outcome is the same.59 Rational selfish individuals dealing with other rational selfish individuals will never sacrifice anything to the public good, since it would be a waste.60 That is what makes the situation a dilemma.61
Hobbes constructed his state of nature, using logic, not using historical data. The state of nature, for him, is rather a kind of thought experiment after the manner of experimental science.62 Hobbes is the, again, the great founder of what we might call, among others, is the experimental method in social and political science.63
How can we escape the horror of the Hobbesian state of nature? By establishing a sovereign by means of a social contract. He would understand (1) that it is rationally necessary to seek peace; (2) that the way to secure peace is to enter into an agreement with others not to harm one another; and (3) that having entered into such an agreement, it would be irrational, in the sense of self-defeating, to break it for as long as the others kept it.64 By this chain of reasoning, society would be created.65 It would be created by an agreement – a ‘compact’, as Hobbes calls it – made by individuals no one of whom has interest in anyone else’s good per se, but each of whom realizes that his own good can be secured only by agreeing not to harm others in return for their agreement not to harm him.66 But, there must be an enforcer, because Hobbes argues that, “Covenants without the sword are but words, and of no strength to secure a man at all.”67 So the people will have to, “Confer all power and strength upon one Man, or upon one assembly of men, that may reduce all their wills, by plurality of voices, unto one Will . . . This is more than Consent, or Concord; it is a real Unity of them all, in one and the same Person, made by Covenant of every man with every man . . . that Great Leviathan, the Commonwealth, and it comes about when either one man by War subdueth his enemies to his will, or when men agree amongst themselves, to submit to some Man, or Assembly of men, voluntarily, on confidence to be protected by him against all others.”68 The sovereign is created by, but not a party to, the compact.69 He therefore cannot be got rid of because he is in reach of the compact.70 If he could be, his power would not, after all, be sovereign.71
Hobbes remains one of the most impressive and influential of English political theorists.72 He is also, though he several times twits himself on his own timidity, a writer of considerable intellectual courage, who expressed unpopular views at a time when it was dangerous – mortally dangerous, indeed - to do so.73 He also “provides an antidote to the high-minded reasoning of the schoolmen and indeed the Ancients.”74 Starting from a pragmatic assessment of human nature, he strengthens the case for a powerful political and social apparatus organizing our lives.75 And with his interest in the methods of geometry and the natural sciences, he brings a new style of argument to political theorizing that is both more persuasive and more effective.76 But from Hobbes we also obtain a reminder that social organization, however committed to fairness and equality it may be intended to be, being motivated by a struggle between its members, is also inevitably both authoritarian and inegalitarian.77 Virtually all subsequent attempts to treat politics and political behavior philosophically have in some sense had to take Hobbes into account.78

“Though the water running in the fountain be everyone’s, yet who can doubt but that in the pitcher is his only who drew it out?”
-John Locke, Second Treatise79

John Locke was born into a Puritan family in Somerset, England.80 His father was a country lawyer who raised a troop of horse and fought on the parliamentary side in the Civil War.81 Locke went up to Christ Church, Oxford, in 1652.82 Like Hobbes before him, Locke found the old fashioned Scholastic curriculum uncongenial, though his association with Christ Church was to last, with interruptions, for more than thirty years.83 He became a senior student – that is, a Fellow – in 1659.84 In 1667 he became medical adviser and general factotum of Anthony Ashley Cooper, created first Earl of Shaftesbury in 1672.85 When Shaftesbury was appointed Lord Chancellor in 1672, Locke became his secretary.86 Earl Shaftesbury went on to three notable political achievements: he led the opposition to Charles II, he founded the Whig Party, the forerunner of the Liberals, and he pushed Locke into politics.87 John Locke is a kind of ‘lowest common denominator’ of political philosophy, the intellectual forebear of much of today’s political orthodoxy, a role that befits a thinker of a naturally orthodox turn of mind.88 He also “fitted the times very well (Bertrand Russell even described him as the ‘apostle of the Revolution of 1688’).89 His philosophy was actively adopted by contemporary politicians and thinkers; his influence was transmitted to eighteenth-century France through the medium of Voltaire’s writings, and inspired the principles of the French Revolution.90 And his views would spread still more widely, through the writings of Thomas Paine, eventually shaping the American Revolution too.91 Although Locke’s reputation as a philosopher rests almost entirely on the epistemological doctrines expressed in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, he made a great and lasting contribution to political thought.92 This contribution consists mainly in his Two Treatises of Government, especially in the Second Treatise.93 It is usual to regard the First Treatise as being mainly of antiquarian interest.94 It is in the Second Treatise that Locke presents his own ideas.95 The proper title of the treatise is ‘An Essay Concerning the True, Original, Extent, and End of Civil Government.’96 The master of Locke’s own residential college at Oxford, Balliol College, described Mr. Locke as the ‘master of taciturnity’, because he could not discover, through questioning and so on, Locke’s opinions on religious and political matters.97 Before we proceed to his notion of the state of nature, we will first explore some of his major ideas. First is his account of the law of nature. There is no modern thinker that I’m aware of who makes natural law as important to his doctrine as does Locke.98 The law of nature, Locke tells us, “willeth the peace and preservation of all mankind.”99 Locke adds, the “law of nature . . . obliges everyone; and reason which is that law, teaches all mankind who will but consult it, that being all equal and independent, no one ought to harm another in his life, health, liberty, or possessions.”100 Locke also offers the three fundamental rights: life, health, and property. These three rights can never be overruled even by the government. They are also our natural rights, they are pre-political, it means that they are already our rights even before the establishment of the government. The interesting thing about these fundamental rights is that it is paradoxical. There are two reasons for this paradox. The first is that, “our rights are less fully mine.”101 Our rights were given by God. Locke tells us, “For men, being all the workmanship of one Omnipotent and Infinitely Wise Maker, they are his property whose workmanship they are, made to last during his, not one another’s pleasure.”102 The second reason is that, “because our rights are unalienable, they are more deeply mine.”103 These three Lockean fundamental rights influenced the famous 1776 U.S. Declaration of Independence, “We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable rights, that among these are life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness.”104 It’s like the ghost of John Locke who wrote this declaration, not Thomas Jefferson. Every sentence of this declaration has something like a Lockean spirit or fingerprint. This Lockean principle also influenced our present Constitution. Art. III, Sec. I of the 1987 Constitution states that, “No person shall be deprived of life, liberty, or property without due process of law, nor shall any person be denied the equal protection of the laws.”105 Next, his theory of private property. Locke’s “account of property; certainly, in many ways, one of the most characteristic doctrines of Lockean political thought.”106 In the beginning the whole world was America, explains Locke, meaning that the world was an unexploited wilderness, before, through the efforts of people, there came farms and manufactures and buildings and cities.107 With these come trade, and money.108 But although property is the foundation of political society, Locke traces its origin back not to commerce, but to ‘the conjugal union.’109 The first society was between man and wife, and later their children.110 Locke’s view of human nature is that we are very much the property-acquiring animal.111 Locke tells us, “Every man has a property in his own person, this nobody has any right to but himself. The labor of his body and the work of his hands, we may say are properly his.”112 This is one of the major premises of Robert Nozick and other libertarian thinkers, that we own ourselves. Locke continues, “Whatsoever then he removes out of that state of nature has provided and left it in, he has mixed his labor with, and joined to it something that in his own and thereby makes it his property.”113 Locke anticipates Marx’s Labor Theory of Value. Locke continues, “For this labor being the unquestionable property of the laborer no man but he can hence a right, to what that is once joined to, at least where there is enough and as good left in common for others.”114 Locke adds, “As much land as a man tills, plants, improves, cultivates and can use the product of, so much is his property. He by his labor, does as it were, enclose it from the common.”115 One of the most famous passages in the Second Treatise is that, “God gave the world to men in common, but since He gave it to them for their benefit and the greatest conveniences of life that they were capable to draw from it . . . it cannot be supposed He meant it should always remain common and uncultivated. He gave it to the use of the industrious and the rational and not to the fancy or covetousness of the quarrelsome and contentious.”116 Locke seems to suggest, that the state will be a commercial state, that the Lockean republic, the Lockean state will be a commercial republic.117 Labor becomes, for Locke, his source of all value and our title to common ownership and in a remarkable rhetorical series of shifts, he makes not nature, but rather human labor and acquisition the source of property and of unlimited material possessions.118 The new politics of the Lockean state will no longer be concerned with glory, honor, thumos, virtue, but Lockean politics will be sober, will be pedestrian, it will be hedonistic, without sublimity or joy.119 Locke is the author of the doctrine that commerce softens manners, that it makes us less warlike, that it makes us civilized.120 On the ground of Locke’s claim of self-ownership as the foundation of rights and justice, I will offer one of the major criticisms to this view. This is the ‘difference principle’ of one of my favorite political philosophers, John Rawls. First, “Lockean theory of justice, broadly speaking, supports a meritocracy sometimes referred to as ‘equality of opportunity’, that is, what a person does with his or her natural assets belongs exclusively to him, the right to rise or fall belongs exclusively to him.”121 Rawls’ principle “maintains that our natural endowments, our talents, our abilities, our family backgrounds, our history, our unique histories, our place, so to speak, in the social hierarchy, all of these things are from a moral point of view something completely arbitrary.122 None of these are ours in any strong sense of the term.123 They do not belong to us but are the result of a more or less kind of random or arbitrary genetic lottery or social lottery of which I or you happen to be the unique beficiaries.124 No longer can I be regarded as the sole proprietor of my assets or the unique recipient of the advantages or disadvantages I may accrue from them.125 Rawls concludes, I should not be regarded as a possessor but merely the recipient of what talents, capacities, and abilities that I may, again, purely arbitrary happen to possess.126 The difference principle is a principle for institutions, not for individuals.127 This is not to say that the difference principle does not imply duties for individuals – it creates innumerable duties for them.128 It means rather that the difference principle applies in the first instance to regulate economic conventions and legal institutions, such as the market mechanism, the system of property, contract, inheritance, securities, taxation, and so on.129 The direct application of the difference principle to structure economic institutions and its indirect application to individual conduct, exhibit what Rawls means when he says that the ‘primary subject of justice is the basic structure of society.’130 The basic structure of society consists of the arrangement of the political, social, and economic institutions that make social cooperation possible and productive.131 These institutions have a profound influence on individuals’ everyday lives, their characters, desires, and ambitions, as well as their future prospects.132 The difference principle also “requires that economic institutions be designed so that the least advantaged class enjoys a greater share of income, wealth, and economic powers more generally, than it would under any other economic arrangement (with the important qualification that the final distribution is compatible with equal basic liberties and fair equal opportunities).133 We should follow the principle that would be chose under ideal conditions not because it is rational for us to use such a procedure (in the narrow sense of rationality), and not because doing so would maximize total overall utility, but because doing so embodies fundamental values to which Rawls thinks, we are already committed, the values of freedom and equality.134 In structuring a just society, we must also employ what Rawls called ‘the veil of ignorance’. The situation where you don’t know who you will be.135 Using the DP and the veil of ignorance, we can assure that the cake will be sliced equally. There are other important Lockean ideas, that I wish to address, but for the main reason of limiting my paper, I won’t discuss them anymore. These important ideas are the Lockean idea of a limited government (which resembles our present form of government), his ‘Appeal to Heaven’ doctrine or the right of the people to rebel against an unjust government (this doctrine is also embodied in the Art. II, Sec. I, of the 1987 Constitution), and his famous doctrine of consent. Now, let’s proceed to the Lockean version of the state of nature. Like Hobbes, Locke makes use of the idea of a state of nature as an explanatory conceit which to build his political theory.136 As with Hobbes, and despite some ambiguity of language, the argument is not really a historical one.137 Locke does not take Hobbes’ pessimistic view of how ungoverned human beings would behave in relation to each other.138 Unlike Hobbes, he does not depict the state of nature as an intolerable condition in which the amenities of civilization are impossible.139 The drawbacks of Locke’s state of nature would be no worse than ‘inconveniences’.140 The ‘continous inconveniences’ is that men in the state of nature were both the judge and executor of the law of nature. Locke tells us, “The execution of the law of nature is, in that state, put into every man’s hands, whereby everyone has a right to punish the transgressor of that law to such a degree as may hinder its violation.”141 Everyone can enforce the law of nature. Locke adds, “One may destroy a man who makes war upon him . . . for the same reason that he may kill a wolf or a lion; because such man . . . have no other rule, but that of force and violence, and he may be treated as beasts of prey, those dangerous and noxious creatures, that will be sure to destroy the, whenever he feels into their power.”142 How can we escape the ‘inconveniences’ of Locke’s state of nature? Civil government is the proper remedy for the inconveniences of the state of nature.143 Just like his great predecessor Hobbes, we must mutually agree to give up our enforcement power by means of a social contract. Locke tells us, “Men being, as has been said, by nature, all free and equal and independent, no one can be put out of this estate, and subjected to the political power of another, without his own consent . . . when any number of men have, by the consent of every individual, made a community, they have thereby made that community one body, with a power to act as one body, which is only by the will and determination of the majority . . . to move . . . whither the greater force carries it.”144 Locke has no particular view about the form of government should take, as long as it is based on popular consent.145 It may be a republic, but it could be an oligarchy and there might still be a monarch.146 But whatever form the government takes, Locke says, it does need to include some ‘separation of powers’, and sets out fairly precisely the distinction to be made between the law-making part of government – the legislature – and the action-taking part – the executive.147 The executive must have the power to appoint and dismiss the legislature, but it does not make the one superior to the other, rather there exists a ‘fiduciary trust’.148 According to Locke’s view of government, there are only two parties to the trust: the people, who is both trustor and beneficiary, and the legislature, who is trustee.149 The principal characteristic of a trust is the fact that the trustee assumes primarily obligations rather than rights.150 The purpose of the trust is determined by the interest of the beneficiary and not by the will of the trustee.151 The trustee is little more than a servant of both trustor and beneficiary, and he may be recalled by the trustor in the event of neglect of duty.152 Locke also tells us that, “The great and chief end, therefore, of men’s uniting into commonwealths and putting themselves under government is the preservation of their property.”153 Property here is the general term for life, liberty, and estates or possessions. This Lockean idea is also embodied in the famous The Federalist No. 10 of James Madison, “The diversity in the faculties of men from which the rights of property originate, is not less an insuperable obstacle to a uniformity of interests. The protection of these faculties is the first object of government.”154 Locke – jointly, perhaps, with Hobbes – is the most influential of all English political theorist.155 His political writing, like all political writing, is a response to the issues and events of a specific time and place, and reflects a particular perception of those issues and events.156 Locke creates a picture of the world in which ‘rationality’ is the ultimate authority, not God, and certainly not, as Hobbes had insisted brute force.157 He insists that people have certain fundamental rights and also attempt to return the other half of the human race, the female part, to their proper, equal, place in history, the family and government.158 Locke’s legacy is the first, essentially practical, even legalistic, framework and analysis of the workings of society.159 That is his own particular contribution to its evolution.160

“Man is born free; and everywhere he is in chains.” -the citizen of Geneva (Jean-Jacques Rousseau), The Social Contract161

Rousseau was born in Geneva in 1712, the son of a Calvinist watchmaker.162 It was his father who brought him up, his mother having died in childbirth.163 His father also gave Rousseau a great love of books, but otherwise he had little formal education.164 At the age of fifteen he ran away from home and began a life of solitary wandering.165 His was a difficult, hypersensitive personality, with a towering sense of his own genius.166 Although capable of intense friendship, his relationships never lasted.167 After leaving Switzerland, Rousseau lived in Savoy and worked in Italy, before gravitating to Paris, at the time the leading intellectual centre in Europe.168 There he associated with the Enlightenment thinkers – the philosophes – and particularly Diderot.169 Rousseau contributed articles (mainly on musicology) to their great project, the Encyclopedia, but although he subscribed to some of their beliefs he was never a committed member of the group.170 He developed his own ideas that differed radically from their fashionable cult of reason and from establishment orthodoxy.171 Indeed, Rousseau’s most striking characteristic is his originality.172 He changed the thinking of Europe, having an impact on political theory, education, literature, ethics, ideas about the self and its relationship to nature, and much else.173 These influences, together with his elevation of emotion and will above reason, make him the major precursor of the Romantic movement.174 His early ‘Discourses’ offended the philosophes, while his two most famous works, Emile and The Social Contract (both 1762), outraged the authorities, particularly because of their religious content.175 They were burned by the public executioner in both Paris and Geneva, and Rousseau’s arrest was ordered.176 He fled France and spent several years seeking refuge in various countries, but returned in 1767 under an assumed name.177 The authorities turned a blind eye so long as he did not publish.178 He spent his final years living in solitude on the estate of an admirer-patron near Paris.179 Here he studied botany and continued to write, mainly autobiographical works.180 Jean-Jacques Rousseau, offered a complete reversal of the values of the time.181 Rousseau did not think anything of civilization, nor was he impressed by the achievements of science.182 He instead thought primitive man had been happier and better off.183 And he measured people’s value not by their possessions, but by the divine spark that he saw in them all, the immortal soul of Natural Man.184 Rousseau attacked and denigrated all that the philosophes held dear: reason, science, philosophy, progress and intellectual sophistication.185 He extolled the virtues of the common man, his loyalty and patriotism and sense of community, and admired dour, militaristic, anti-intellectual Sparta at the expense of intellectually glittering Athens.186 As against the orthodox doctrine of original sin, Rousseau insisted that human beings are essentially good, and that it is only society that corrupts them.187 Together with Montesquieu, Hume, Smith, and Kant among his contemporaries, Rousseau has exerted the most profound influence on modern European intellectual history, perhaps even surpassing anyone else of his day.188 No other eighteenth-century thinker contributed more major writings in so wide a range of subjects and forms, nor wrote with such sustained passion and eloquence.189 No one else managed through both his works and his life to excite or disturb public imagination so deeply.190 Almost alone among the seminal figures of the Enlightenment, he subjected the main currents of the world he inhabited to the most inspired censure, even while channeling their direction, and when French Revolutionary leaders later seized their opportunity to ignite the unity of political practice and theory, it was to his doctrines above all that they professed their allegiance.191 He was also an unscrupulous and selfish man who, despite the fine words of his child-centred educational philosophy, packed his own five illegitimate children off to the harsh world of the local foundling home, and refused even to see them.192 Rousseau was insecure too, convinced that everyone was out to get him, and considered offers of help always to be trickery.193 He constantly complained of being ‘misrepresented’ and by the end of his life was almost certainly suffering from the madness of full-blown paranoia.194 Before we proceed to the Rousseaunian state of nature, we have to consider first some of his major ideas. First his account of amour-propre and amour de soi-meme. The latter is a “sort of self-love.”195 The former “is what moves every individual to value himself more than any other, which inspires all of the evils in society, and is the true source of honor, the desire to be recognized and esteemed by others.”196 Amour-propre is not a natural sentiment but a sentiment that is relative and artificial, could only have come into being once we enter society in some ways.197 How did that happen?198 Rousseau speculates about this and, again, this is part of his hypothetical or conjectural history.199 He speculates that amour-propre began to arise and develop as soon as people began to gather around a hut or a tree and to look at one another, as soon as we became conscious of the gaze of another, and it is from that gaze, from the look or gaze of another, that the passion of vanity was born.200 So the rise of this passion to be seen, to be seen to be best at something, produced in many people again, as he puts it, pride and vanity from some shame and envy on the part of others and from this fatal compound grew tendencies that were, as he says, fatal to our happiness and innocence.201 The “amour-propre is presented . . . in largely negative terms but it is also related to something positive, in many ways, for the development of humanity in society, the desire felt by all people once we enter society, to be accorded some kind of recognition or respect by those around us.202 That too is a part of amour-propre, the desire to be seen and recognized and respected.203 The desire for recognition, he says, is at the root of our sense of justice and underlying this, I think, is the intuition powerful and in many ways I think deeply true, that our feelings, beliefs, opinions and attitudes be acknowledged and respected by others around us, that we matter in some way.204 When we feel that our opinions are slighted, when others do not recognize our worth, we feel angry about this and this need for recognition, which is part of this passion of amour-propre, is for Rousseau also a cornerstone of justice but it is also, as he says, at the same time the demand for recognition can easily become cruel and violent as we demand this from others.205 Rousseau tells us, “As soon as men had begun mutually to value one another and the idea of esteem was formed in their minds, each one claimed to have a right to it, each one claimed to have a right to esteem or recognition, and it no longer possible for anyone to be lacking it with impunity. From this came the first duties of civility even among savages and from this every voluntary wrong became an outrage. Every time someone was harmed or injured, it became an outrage because along with the harm that resulted from the injury, the offended party saw in it contempt for his person, which often was more insufferable than the harm itself . . . each man punished the contempt shown him in a matter proportionate to the esteem in which he held himself. Acts of revenge became terrible and men became bloodthirsty and cruel.”206 It sounds like the “war of all against all” notion of Hobbes, isn’t it? Next is his famous notion of the general will. All laws would have to be passed unanimously.207 From what we know of democratic politics of any kind, this would seem to be impossible.208 It is to solve this problem that Rousseau introduces his most famous doctrine, that of the General Will.209 The basic idea is that each one of us wills or desires a variety of things, but among the things that each of us desires is the good of the community in which we live.210 It is the aggregate of this desire for the communal good that Rousseau calls the General Will.211 It follows from this that if a law is passed that is in accord with the General Will, then in obeying this law we are in a sense obeying ourselves.212 Conversely, since it is precisely by obeying the General Will that we obey ourselves and are therefore free, disobeying the General Will means that we deny our own freedom.213 This explains Rousseau’s infamous and chilling remark about those who refuse to obey the law being ‘forced to be free’.214 Rousseau is not using here the usual common-sense or ‘negative’ notion of freedom as simply doing what we want, but rather a ‘positive’ notion of freedom that insists that we are only truly free when we are obeying our ‘higher selves’ (in this case our desire for the common good) rather than our baser selfish instincts (when we are merely a ‘slave to our passions’).215 Rousseau tells us, “Each of us puts his person and all his power in common under the supreme direction of the general will, and, in our corporate capacity, we receive each member as an indivisible part of the whole.”216 This idea of general will influenced the famous solitary man, Immanuel Kant. Kant “called Rousseau the Newton of the moral universal.”217 Kant’s entire moral philosophy is a kind of deepened and radicalized Rousseauianism where what Rousseau called the general will is transmuted into what Kant calls the rational will and the categorical imperative.218 Kant says, “Act only on that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law.”219 By ‘maxim’, Kant means a rule or principle that gives the reason for your action.220 He is saying, in effect, that we should act only on principles that we could universalize without contradiction.221 The general will is “a good example of methodological collectivism . . . Rousseau . . . does not believe that studying the individual actions we can understand what is society and what the need of the society is.”222 But the general will “is a very disturbing idea . . . which opens Rousseau up to a totalitarian interpretation . . . he argues that the government knows better.”223 In fact, “J.L. Talmon argued that Rousseau, despite his reputation as the first modern democratic thinker, was in fact the father of modern totalitarianism.”224 There are many other important Rousseaunian notions such as his famous educational philosophy, his nurture rather than nature argument, his idea of the bourgeoisie, his idea of the true citizen, etc. Now let us consider his notion of the state of nature. Rousseau follows in the footsteps of his great predecessors, particularly Hobbes and Locke in attempting to understand the hypothetical or conjectural state of nature.225 In many ways, he praises and follows Hobbes and Locke in doing this but suggests that they never really took the problem of nature seriously enough.226 So when Hobbes tells us or when he attributes to natural man certain warlike propensities, Rousseau figures that this cannot be right.227 War and the passions that give rise to war can only come into being once we are in society.228 The state of war is really simply the state of society.229 This cannot be told for natural man because the natural conditions had no social relationships of this sort and you might say his statement was ditto for John Locke.230 When Locke attributes to us in the state of nature certain qualities of rationality, of industry, of acquisitiveness, these too, Rousseau complains, are only qualities that we can acquire in the light of society.231 Property entails social relations between persons, relations of justice and injustice, and man in a state of nature is not a social animal.232 So it is clear for Rousseau that human nature is something infinitely more remote and strange than any of his predecessors had ever imagined.233 When Aristotle said that man is the rational being because we possess speech or logos Rousseau says ‘wrong again.’234 Language is dependent upon society and could only have developed over literally thousands of generations and cannot be a property of natural man.235 Rousseau specifies two qualities that set as apart.236 The first is the quality of freedom or what he calls free agency although he understands this in a very specific way.237 He connects freedom, to what he calls the phenomenon or the quality, the faculty of perfectibility.238 Perfectibility, for Rousseau, suggests an openness, a sort of virtually unlimited openness to change.239 We are the species who not only have the freedom to do this or that but we are the species who have the freedom, as it were, to become this or that.240 And it is our very openness to change that accounts for our mutability over time.241 Our nature is not confined in advance to what it may become; rather, our nature, for Rousseau, is uniquely suited to alter and transform itself as circumstances change and as we adapt and adopt to new and unforeseen situations.242 He believed it was impossible to discover from the works of any of these or other political thinkers (Hobbes and Locke) why men in the state of nature should seek protection from their neighbours, but he thought their ideas collectively did none the less explain how individuals might have established as legitimate just those determinate and fixed relations which form the distinctions between them in corrupt society.243 According to Rousseau, confronting Hobbes in particular, it was true that men must have developed all their social obligations so as to protect their lives and their possessions, but since they could not have been at war, nor owned any property, nor had any ambitions to dominate or any reason to fear one another, in their natural state, it was inconceivable that they should originally have felt the need for such security (P iii 153–4; G 151).244 The state of nature could have contained no endogenous factors to drive its inhabitants out of it, and sentiments of envy or distrust, which made persons apprehensive for their safety or fearful of losing their possessions, were, in his view, simply not appropriate to men who lived contentedly alone.245 They had attributed to savage man a set of traits which he could have acquired only in society, and since they had failed to distinguish our social qualities from our natural endowments, their portraits of our original conduct and behavior had been too thickly drawn, encrusted with the accretions of our development.246 Having set themselves the task of explaining the state of nature, Rousseau contends in an important and lengthy footnote of his second Discourse, these thinkers did not hesitate to transpose their ideas across centuries of time, as if men in isolation already lived amongst their neighbours (P iii 218; G 216).247 Worse still, they had proposed that some of our most fatal vices should be authorized by law.248 Now his idea of the Social Contract. Rousseau is clear that it is not possible for men to return to the freedom of the state of nature, but it is possible, he insists, to exchange that freedom for the freedom of the citizen.249 This is done through an act of association that creates the social entity and in which all give up rights and become subjects while at the same time receiving rights as citizens and members of the sovereign.250 Rousseau tells us, “The problem is to find a form of association which will defend and protect with the whole common force the person and goods of each associate, and in which each, while uniting himself with all, may still obey himself alone, and remain as free as before. This is the fundamental problem of which the Social Contract provides the solution.”251 Rousseau adds, “. . . properly understood, may be reduced to one – the total alienation of each associate, together with all his rights, to the whole community.”252 The total alienation clause as it were, is Rousseau’s manner of ensuring that the term of the contract are the same for everyone.253 But secondly, when we alienate ourselves, it is crucial, he says, that this be done or given to the entire community, for only then he wants to argue, is the individual beholden not to any private will or any private association, or to some other person but to the general will, the will of the entire community.254 The social contract is the foundation of the general will which is, for Rousseau, the only legitimate government.255 Since everyone combines to make up this will, when we give ourselves over to it entirely, he wants to argue, we do nothing more than obey ourselves.256 There is no doubt that Rousseau is the key figure in the development of democratic thought.257 All previous significant thinkers, from Plato onwards, had regarded democracy with suspicion: it was usually equated with the rule of the mob, and at best could only be an element in a wider system that thereby allowed a degree of participation for the better off.258 It was Rousseau who developed the concept of the sovereignty of the people, and he was the first to insist upon the fitness and right of ordinary people to participate in the political system as full citizens.259 Rousseau’s recipe for human society can be expressed in just one word: ‘Freedom’.260 Rousseau offers us a fairly implausible idea of what this might be, and supposes it to be in conflict and opposition to the structures of modern societies.261 But Rousseau’s legacy is still important as a reminder of non-material values, and a more optimistic if romanticised notion of humanity.262 What he offers us may be largely false and often is hopelessly impractical, but it is also always an important, alternative understanding of ourselves.263

Leviathan by Thomas Hobbes published in 1651264

Second Treatise26

Social Contract published in 1762266

Which of the three accounts of human nature: Hobbesian, Lockean, or Rousseaunian?

Even though the three accounts of state of nature from our three contractarian theorists lack the necessary anthropological or even archaeological data, we have to answer the question on the basis of its philosophical content.
I agree with the notion of the Monster of Malmesbury that we are naturally selfish and self-interested. Weber also has the same sentiments. Weber “assume that humans were self-interested by nature, and that self-interested behavior was to be expected in all societies.”267 Society determined how self-interest manifested itself, but the self-interest was there all along.268 He believed that struggle was one of the great, ineradicable principles of social life.269
I also strongly believe with the notion of Monster of Malmesbury that we are all in “a perpetual and restless desire of power after power, that ceaseth only in death.”270 The definition of power by Weber is the most suitable for me. Weber defines power as “. . . the chance of a man or a number of men to realize their own will . . . even against the resistance of others.”271 The essence of stratification is power, someone has power over someone else.272 It follows that I reject the optimistic view of the ‘master of taciturnity’ regarding the state of nature.
I also believe that, naturally, we have necrophobia (the fear of death). So it follows, that I am not with the side of Rousseau regarding his argument that our fear of death was a product of society. Rousseau “said naturally we would know how to suffer and how to die, but we are being sort of indoctrinated to fear death and have anxieties in . . . life.”273 My stand would be, “what we fear and seek to avoid more than anything else is death, death being precisely the event that makes the further continuance of felicity impossible.”274 Death is the end275
I may sound pessimistic, but the state of nature is “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short.”276

1. Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/h/hobbes/thomas/h68l/. Accessed August 5-10, 2013.
2. Adams, Ian & R.W. Dyson. 2007. Fifty Major Political Thinkers, 2nd edition. U.S.A.: Routledge: Taylor and Francis Group. p. 46
3. Ibid.
4. Ibid.
5. Ibid.
6. Cohen, Martin. 2001. Political Philosophy: From Plato to Mao. London: Pluto Press. p.50
7. Ibid.
8. Prof. Ivan Szelenyi Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 2- Hobbes: Authority, Human Rights, and Social Order [September 8, 2008]. SOCY- 151: Foundations of Modern Social Theory. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/sociology/socy-151/lecture-2. Accessed August 6, 2013.
9. Cohen, Martin. 2001. Political Philosophy: From Plato to Mao. London: Pluto Press. p.49
10. Ibid.
11. Ibid.
12. Ibid.
13. Ibid.
14. Ibid., p. 50
15. Adams, Ian & R.W. Dyson. 2007. Fifty Major Political Thinkers, 2nd edition. U.S.A.: Routledge: Taylor and Francis Group. p. 48
16. Ibid.
17. Ibid.
18. Ibid.
19. Ibid.
20. Ibid.
21. Ibid.
22. Ibid., p. 54
23. Ibid.
24. Ibid., p. 48
25. Ibid.
26. Prof. Steven Smith Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 12- The Sovereign State: Hobbes, Leviathan [October 18, 2006]. PLSC-114: Introduction to Political Philosophy. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/political-science/plsc-114/lecture-12. Accessed August 6, 2013.
27. Ibid.
28. Prof. Steven Smith Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 13- The Sovereign State: Hobbes, Leviathan [October 23, 2006]. PLSC-114: Introduction to Political Philosophy. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/political-science/plsc-114/lecture-13. Accessed August 6, 2013.
29. Ibid.
30. Ibid.
31. Ibid.
32. Berger, Peter & Thomas Luckmann. 1966. The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. New York: Doubleday and Company, Inc. p. 172
33. Prof. Steven Smith Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 13- The Sovereign State: Hobbes, Leviathan [October 23, 2006]. PLSC-114: Introduction to Political Philosophy. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/political-science/plsc-114/lecture-13. Accessed August 6, 2013.
34. Ibid.
35. Ibid.
36. Ibid.
37. Ibid.
38. Ibid.
39. Cohen, Martin. 2001. Political Philosophy: From Plato to Mao. London: Pluto Press. p.59
40. During her lecture given at the Department of Sociology and Anthropology, Polytechnic University of the Philippines-Manila last August 10, 2013. Camille Bacale-Ocampo is a sociology graduate at the prestigious University of the Philippines-Diliman, and also a law degree holder. She is currently taking her Masteral Studies at the elite Ateneo de Manila University. She is a regular professor at the Polytechnic University of the Philippines-Manila.
41. Ibid.
42. Prof. Steven Smith Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 14- The Sovereign State: Hobbes, Leviathan [October 25, 2006]. PLSC-114: Introduction to Political Philosophy. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/political-science/plsc-114/lecture-14. Accessed August 6, 2013.
43. De Leon, Hector S. & Hector M. De Leon Jr. 2011. Textbook on the Philippine Constitution. Quezon City. Rex Printing Company, Inc. p. 751
44. Cohen, Martin. 2001. Political Philosophy: From Plato to Mao. London: Pluto Press. p.49
45. Ibid., p. 52
46. Ibid.
47. Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/h/hobbes/thomas/h68l/. Accessed August 5-10, 2013.
48. Cohen, Martin. 2001. Political Philosophy: From Plato to Mao. London: Pluto Press. p.52
49. Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/h/hobbes/thomas/h68l/. Accessed August 5-10, 2013.
50. Prof. Steven Smith Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 13- The Sovereign State: Hobbes, Leviathan [October 23, 2006]. PLSC-114: Introduction to Political Philosophy. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/political-science/plsc-114/lecture-13. Accessed August 6, 2013.
51. Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/h/hobbes/thomas/h68l/. Accessed August 5-10, 2013.
52. Cohen, Martin. 2001. Political Philosophy: From Plato to Mao. London: Pluto Press. p.55
53. Ibid.
54. Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/h/hobbes/thomas/h68l/. Accessed August 5-10, 2013.
55. Ibid.
56. Collins, Randall. 1994. Four Sociological Traditions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 158
57. Ibid.
58. Ibid., pp. 158-159
59. Ibid., p. 159
60. Ibid.
61. Ibid.
62. Prof. Steven Smith Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 12- The Sovereign State: Hobbes, Leviathan [October 18, 2006]. PLSC-114: Introduction to Political Philosophy. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/political-science/plsc-114/lecture-12. Accessed August 6, 2013.
63. Ibid.
64. Adams, Ian & R.W. Dyson. 2007. Fifty Major Political Thinkers, 2nd edition. U.S.A.: Routledge: Taylor and Francis Group. p. 51
65. Ibid.
66. Ibid.
67. Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/h/hobbes/thomas/h68l/. Accessed August 5-10, 2013.
68. Ibid.
69. Adams, Ian & R.W. Dyson. 2007. Fifty Major Political Thinkers, 2nd edition. U.S.A.: Routledge: Taylor and Francis Group. p. 52
70. Ibid.
71. Ibid.
72. Cohen, Martin. 2001. Political Philosophy: From Plato to Mao. London: Pluto Press. p.52
73. Ibid., p. 53
74. Ibid., p.63
75. Ibid.
76. Ibid.
77. Ibid.
78. Adams, Ian & R.W. Dyson. 2007. Fifty Major Political Thinkers, 2nd edition. U.S.A.: Routledge: Taylor and Francis Group. p. 53
79. Locke, John. 1823. Two Treatises of Government: In the Former, The False Principles and Foundation of Sir Robert Filmer, and His Followers, Are Detected and Overthrown: The Latter, Is an Essay Concerning the Original, Extent, and End, of Civil Government. London: Prepared by Rod Hay for the McMaster University Archive of the History of Economic Thought. p. 117
80. Adams, Ian & R.W. Dyson. 2007. Fifty Major Political Thinkers, 2nd edition. U.S.A.: Routledge: Taylor and Francis Group. p. 57
81. Ibid.
82. Ibid.
83. Ibid.
84. Ibid.
85. Ibid.
86. Ibid.
87. Cohen, Martin. 2001. Political Philosophy: From Plato to Mao. London: Pluto Press. p. 66
88. Ibid.
89. Ibid., p. 67
90. Ibid.
91. Ibid.
92. Adams, Ian & R.W. Dyson. 2007. Fifty Major Political Thinkers, 2nd edition. U.S.A.: Routledge: Taylor and Francis Group. p. 58
93. Ibid.
94. Ibid.
95. Ibid.
96. Ibid.
97. Prof. Steven Smith Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 15- Constitutional Government: Locke, Second Treatise (1-5) [October 30, 2006]. PLSC-114: Introduction to Political Philosophy. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/political-science/plsc-114/lecture-15. Accessed August 7, 2013.
98. Ibid.
99. Locke, John. 1823. Two Treatises of Government: In the Former, The False Principles and Foundation of Sir Robert Filmer, and His Followers, Are Detected and Overthrown: The Latter, Is an Essay Concerning the Original, Extent, and End, of Civil Government. London: Prepared by Rod Hay for the McMaster University Archive of the History of Economic Thought. p. 108
100. Ibid.
101. Prof. Michael Sandel Ph.D. of Harvard University. Justice: Lecture 4- This Land is my Land. http://www.justiceharvard.org/2011/02/episode-04/#watch. Accessed August 7, 2013.
102. Locke, John. 1823. Two Treatises of Government: In the Former, The False Principles and Foundation of Sir Robert Filmer, and His Followers, Are Detected and Overthrown: The Latter, Is an Essay Concerning the Original, Extent, and End, of Civil Government. London: Prepared by Rod Hay for the McMaster University Archive of the History of Economic Thought. p. 107
103.Prof. Michael Sandel Ph.D. of Harvard University. Justice: Lecture 4- This Land is my Land. http://www.justiceharvard.org/2011/02/episode-04/#watch. Accessed August 7, 2013.
104. Burns James, J. W. Peltason, Thomas Cronin, & David Magleby. 1993. Government by the People, 15th edition. U.S.A.: Prentice Hall. p. 584
105. De Leon, Hector S. & Hector M. De Leon Jr. 2011. Textbook on the Philippine Constitution. Quezon City. Rex Printing Company, Inc. p. 127
106. Prof. Steven Smith Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 15- Constitutional Government: Locke, Second Treatise (1-5) [October 30, 2006]. PLSC-114: Introduction to Political Philosophy. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/political-science/plsc-114/lecture-15. Accessed August 7, 2013.
107. Cohen, Martin. 2001. Political Philosophy: From Plato to Mao. London: Pluto Press. p. 72
108. Ibid.
109. Ibid., pp. 72-73
110. Ibid., p. 73
111. Prof. Steven Smith Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 15- Constitutional Government: Locke, Second Treatise (1-5) [October 30, 2006]. PLSC-114: Introduction to Political Philosophy. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/political-science/plsc-114/lecture-15. Accessed August 7, 2013.
112. Locke, John. 1823. Two Treatises of Government: In the Former, The False Principles and Foundation of Sir Robert Filmer, and His Followers, Are Detected and Overthrown: The Latter, Is an Essay Concerning the Original, Extent, and End, of Civil Government. London: Prepared by Rod Hay for the McMaster University Archive of the History of Economic Thought. p. 116
113. Ibid.
114. Ibid.
115. Ibid.
116. Ibid.
117. Prof. Steven Smith Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 15- Constitutional Government: Locke, Second Treatise (1-5) [October 30, 2006]. PLSC-114: Introduction to Political Philosophy. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/political-science/plsc-114/lecture-15. Accessed August 7, 2013.
118. Ibid.
119. Ibid.
120. Ibid.
121. Prof. Steven Smith Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 17- Constitutional Government: Locke, Second Treatise (13-19) [November 6, 2006]. PLSC-114: Introduction to Political Philosophy. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/political-science/plsc-114/lecture-17. August 7, 2013.
122. Ibid.
123. Ibid.
124. Ibid.
125. Ibid.
126. Ibid.
127. Freeman, Samuel. 2007. Rawls. London: Routledge Taylor and Francis Group. p. 99
128. Ibid.
129. Ibid.
130. Ibid., p.101
131. Ibid.
132. Ibid.
133. Ibid., p. 106
134. Christman, John. 2002. Social and Political Philosophy: A Contemporary Introduction. London: Routledge Taylor and Francis Group. p. 74
135. Prof. Tamar Gendler Ph,D. of Yale University. Of the People, by the People, for the People? The Rawls-Nozick Debates as an Introduction to the Philosophy of Politics and Economics. http://floatinguniversity.com/lectures-gendler. Accessed August 10, 2013.
136. Adams, Ian & R.W. Dyson. 2007. Fifty Major Political Thinkers, 2nd edition. U.S.A.: Routledge: Taylor and Francis Group. p. 59
137. Ibid.
138. Ibid.
139. Ibid., p. 60
140. Ibid.
141. Locke, John. 1823. Two Treatises of Government: In the Former, The False Principles and Foundation of Sir Robert Filmer, and His Followers, Are Detected and Overthrown: The Latter, Is an Essay Concerning the Original, Extent, and End, of Civil Government. London: Prepared by Rod Hay for the McMaster University Archive of the History of Economic Thought. p. 108
142. Ibid.
143. Ibid.
144. Ibid.
145. Cohen, Martin. 2001. Political Philosophy: From Plato to Mao. London: Pluto Press. p. 74
146. Ibid.
147. Ibid., pp. 74-75
148. Ibid., p. 75
149. Ebenstein, W. & A. Ebenstein. 2000. Great Political Thinkers: Plato to the Present. Singapore: Thomson. p. 366
150. Ibid.
151. Ibid.
152. Ibid.
153. Locke, John. 1823. Two Treatises of Government: In the Former, The False Principles and Foundation of Sir Robert Filmer, and His Followers, Are Detected and Overthrown: The Latter, Is an Essay Concerning the Original, Extent, and End, of Civil Government. London: Prepared by Rod Hay for the McMaster University Archive of the History of Economic Thought. p. 159
154. Pole, J.R. 1987. The American Constitution For and Against: The Federalist and Anti-Federalist Papers. New York: Hill and Wong. p. 151
155. Adams, Ian & R.W. Dyson. 2007. Fifty Major Political Thinkers, 2nd edition. U.S.A.: Routledge: Taylor and Francis Group. p. 63
156. Ibid.
157. Cohen, Martin. 2001. Political Philosophy: From Plato to Mao. London: Pluto Press. p. 79
158. Ibid.
159. Ibid.
160. Ibid.
161. Adams, Ian & R.W. Dyson. 2007. Fifty Major Political Thinkers, 2nd edition. U.S.A.: Routledge: Taylor and Francis Group. p. 73
162. Ibid.
163. Ibid.
164. Ibid.
165. Ibid.
166. Ibid.
167. Ibid.
168. Ibid.
169. Ibid.
170. Ibid.
171. Ibid.
172. Ibid.
173. Ibid.
174. Ibid.
175. Ibid.
176. Ibid., pp. 73-74
177. Ibid., p. 74
178. Ibid.
179. Ibid.
180. Ibid.
181. Cohen, Martin. 2001. Political Philosophy: From Plato to Mao. London: Pluto Press. p. 82
182. Ibid.
183. Ibid.
184. Ibid.
185. Adams, Ian & R.W. Dyson. 2007. Fifty Major Political Thinkers, 2nd edition. U.S.A.: Routledge: Taylor and Francis Group. p. 74
186. Ibid.
187. Ibid.
188. Wokler, Robert. 1995. Rousseau: A Very Short Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 1
189. Ibid.
190. Ibid.
191. Ibid.
192. Cohen, Martin. 2001. Political Philosophy: From Plato to Mao. London: Pluto Press. p. 83
193. Ibid.
194. Ibid.
195. Prof. Steven Smith Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 19- Democracy and Participation: Rousseau, Discourse on Inequality (Part II) [November 13, 2006]. PLSC-114: Introduction to Political Philosophy. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/political-science/plsc-114/lecture-19. Accessed August 9, 2013.
196. Ibid.
197. Ibid.
198. Ibid.
199. Ibid.
200. Ibid.
201. Ibid.
202. Ibid.
203. Ibid.
204. Ibid.
205. Ibid.
206. Ibid.
207. Adams, Ian & R.W. Dyson. 2007. Fifty Major Political Thinkers, 2nd edition. U.S.A.: Routledge: Taylor and Francis Group. p. 76
208. Ibid.
209. Ibid.
210. Ibid.
211. Ibid.
212. Ibid.
213. Ibid.
214. Ibid.
215. Ibid.
216. Social Science II Committee. 1992. Readings in Social Science II: Social, Economic, and Political Thought. Quezon City: University of the Philippines Press. p. 130
217. Prof. Steven Smith Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 20- Democracy and Participation: Rousseau, Social Contract, I-II [November 15, 2006]. PLSC-114: Introduction to Political Philosophy. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/political-science/plsc-114/lecture-20. Accessed August 9, 2013.
218. Ibid.
219. Sandel, Michael J. 2009. Justice: What’s the Right Thing to do? U.S.A.: Farrar, Strauss, and Giroux. p. 120
220. Ibid.
221. Ibid.
222. Prof. Ivan Szelenyi Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 6- Rousseau on State of Nature and Education [September 17, 2008]. SOCY- 151: Foundations of Modern Social Theory. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/sociology/socy-151/lecture-6. Accessed August 10, 2013.
223. Ibid.
224. Adams, Ian & R.W. Dyson. 2007. Fifty Major Political Thinkers, 2nd edition. U.S.A.: Routledge: Taylor and Francis Group. p. 79
225. Prof. Steven Smith Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 18- Democracy and Participation: Rousseau, Discourse on Inequality (Author’s Preface, Part I) [November 8, 2006]. PLSC-114: Introduction to Political Philosophy. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/political-science/plsc-114/lecture-18. Accessed August 9, 2013.
226. Ibid.
227. Ibid.
228. Ibid.
229. Ibid.
230. Ibid.
231. Ibid.
232. Ibid.
233. Ibid.
234. Ibid.
235. Ibid.
236. Ibid.
237. Ibid.
238. Ibid.
239. Ibid.
240. Ibid.
241. Ibid.
242. Ibid.
243. Wokler, Robert. 1995. Rousseau: A Very Short Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 49
244. Ibid.
245. Ibid.
246. Ibid., p. 53
247. Ibid.
248. Ibid.
249. Adams, Ian & R.W. Dyson. 2007. Fifty Major Political Thinkers, 2nd edition. U.S.A.: Routledge: Taylor and Francis Group. p. 75
250. Ibid.
251. Social Science II Committee. 1992. Readings in Social Science II: Social, Economic, and Political Thought. Quezon City: University of the Philippines Press. p. 129
252. Ibid.
253. Prof. Steven Smith Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 20- Democracy and Participation: Rousseau, Social Contract, I-II [November 15, 2006]. PLSC-114: Introduction to Political Philosophy. Open Yale Courses. . http://oyc.yale.edu/political-science/plsc-114/lecture-20. Accessed August 9, 2013.
254. Ibid.
255. Ibid.
256. Ibid.
257. Adams, Ian & R.W. Dyson. 2007. Fifty Major Political Thinkers, 2nd edition. U.S.A.: Routledge: Taylor and Francis Group. p. 79
258. Ibid.
259. Ibid.
260. Cohen, Martin. 2001. Political Philosophy: From Plato to Mao. London: Pluto Press. p. 95
261. Ibid.
262. Ibid.
263. Ibid.
264. The image was taken from: Craig Edward. 2002. Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 106
265. The image was taken from: http://www.google.com.ph/search?q=original+frontispiece+of+second+treatise&bav=on.2,or.r_qf.&bvm=bv.50723672,d.aGc,pv.xjs.s.en_US.kOth2ObowFc.O&biw=1137&bih=725&um=1&ie=UTF-8&hl=en&tbm=isch&source=og&sa=N&tab=wi&ei=B_MKUu-tLqiQiQeCzIDYBg#bav=on.2,or.r_qf.&fp=a91aea830d00bed6&hl=en&q=original+frontispiece+of+second+treatise+by+jon+locke&sa=1&tbm=isch&um=1&facrc=_&imgdii=_&imgrc=xPPr8nhAHG1KLM%3A%3BK5gmBSZF2w3x1M%3Bhttp%253A%252F%252Fwww.loc.gov%252Fexhibits%252Fworld%252Fimages%252Fs38.1.jpg%3Bhttp%253A%252F%252Fwww.loc.gov%252Fexhibits%252Fworld%252Fworld-object.html%3B640%3B981. Accessed August 13, 2013.
266. The image was taken from: Wokler, Robert. 1995. Rousseau: A Very Short Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 83
267. Sanderson, Stephen K. 1999. Macrosociology: An Introduction to Human Societies, 4th edition. New York: Addison Wesley Longman, Inc. p. 11
268. Ibid.
269. Ibid.
270. Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/h/hobbes/thomas/h68l/. Accessed August 5-10, 2013.
271. Goodwin, Glenn A. & Joseph A. Scimecca. 2006. Classical Sociological Theory: Rediscovering the Promise of Sociology. Canada: Thomson Wadsworth. P. 181
272. Ibid.
273. Prof. Ivan Szelenyi Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 6- Rousseau on State of Nature and Education [September 17, 2008]. SOCY- 151: Foundations of Modern Social Theory. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/sociology/socy-151/lecture-6. Accessed August 10, 2013.
274. Adams, Ian & R.W. Dyson. 2007. Fifty Major Political Thinkers, 2nd edition. U.S.A.: Routledge: Taylor and Francis Group. p. 49
275. Prof. Shelly Kagan Ph.D. of Yale University. Lecture 16- Dying Alone; The Badness of Death, Part I [March 8, 2007]. PHIL- 176: Death. Open Yale Courses. http://oyc.yale.edu/philosophy/phil-176/lecture-16. Accessed August 11, 2013.
276. Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/h/hobbes/thomas/h68l/. Accessed August 5-10, 2013.

You May Also Find These Documents Helpful

  • Good Essays

    For the past many years, people have been trying to figure out the relationship between the government and nature of man. The theories of Thomas Hobbes, John Locke and Jean Jacques Rousseau about the connection between nature of man and the government have been debated for many years. These three philosophers have remarkably influenced the way our system works today. Although each theory had its flaws and merits, Jean Jacques Rousseau’s theory is superior in comparison to Thomas Hobbes and John Locke.…

    • 514 Words
    • 3 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    he founding fathers immerged from the British Colonists to become pillars in American history. The revolutionary leaders were immersed with knowledge of educational writings from scholars such as, Thomas Hobbes and John Locke, among many more. The knowledge had an immense impact, on the foundations, principles and rights, the revolutionary leaders fought so passionately to establish.…

    • 185 Words
    • 1 Page
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    The lack of an impartial judge is a defining characteristic of the state of nature, and this lack of a common judge can lead to confusion and violence therefore leading to the state of war. The state of nature and the state of war are not two separate concepts but the state of nature has the fundamental problem and civil government is the solution for the problems of the state of nature.…

    • 397 Words
    • 2 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    Lord of the Flies: Hobbes vs. Locke In the novel, Lord of The Flies by William Golding, several young boys are stranded on an island and must maintain civilization on their own with no real authority. Their attempt at maintaining a peaceful and civilized state between each other can help to explain the theories of philosophy stated by Jack Hobbes and John Locke. In Locke’s philosophy, he states that people are naturally good. He believes that is in our nature, as humans, to be good people and do what it is that we know is right and what we are told is right.…

    • 584 Words
    • 3 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Satisfactory Essays

    Rousseau Vs Hobbes

    • 209 Words
    • 1 Page

    In favor of Hobbes, he does make several valid points. His theory in regards to constant competition applies to this day, as people constantly find themselves in situations where they meet others that are of equal physical strengths and could be faced with a conflict as a result. Despite the points that Hobbes makes, his theory is overall negative, as living in a constant state of fear and paranoia is absolutely no way to live one’s life. Rousseau is very pertinent to remind others of how life was before society and technology took over. Life was extremely simple, and everyone was fairly alright with living alone and focusing on themselves and their life. If today’s society was the same as it was over a thousand years ago, almost no one would…

    • 209 Words
    • 1 Page
    Satisfactory Essays
  • Satisfactory Essays

    Locke Vs Hobbes

    • 184 Words
    • 1 Page

    Throughout history, people have debated about what government is, and what is the purpose of it. Should the government dictate people's lives and tell them what to do? Should the government be permissive and just allow the people take care of themselves and not step in? Should there be an in between? Two very influential philosophers from the 17th century Enlightenment, John Locke and Thomas Hobbes, are preeminent influences on how people see what a government is and what role it should take. They both were renowned influences in many governments, even to this day. Locke took the side that people are naturally good, and that they should rule themselves. While on the other hand, Hobbes said that humans are naturally brutish and evil,…

    • 184 Words
    • 1 Page
    Satisfactory Essays
  • Better Essays

    Hobbes vs Locke

    • 1466 Words
    • 6 Pages

    Thomas Hobbes, a student of Descartes, was born in 1588 and lived through some terrible moments of human history, until he died in 1679. The Civil War, public executions, and The Spanish Armada negatively impacted Hobbes and his view of human nature. During his life it was dangerous to question the government, and surely man had no right to rebel. This negative opinion is further emphasized in Hobbes political theories, in which he concluded humans were selfish and ruthless. Hobbes believed that he and fear were born together. Oppositely, John Lock was born in 1632 and lived through peaceful moments in human history, until he died in 1704. He witnessed The Glorious Revolution and The Declaration of Rights, both in 1689. Society was tolerant and relatively free during this time. This peaceful transmission of power was reflected in his political theories.…

    • 1466 Words
    • 6 Pages
    Better Essays
  • Good Essays

    After graduation from Oxford, he was hired by the Cavendish family to educate the son of William Cavendish, the 1st Earl of Devonshire. He became good friends with William Cavendish and traveled with him. After a sudden death of William Cavendish in 1628, he soon believed that people die young when with an “excessive indulgence in good living”. In November 1631, Hobbes came back and tutored the 3rd Earl of Devonshire. He had a Grand Tour of Europe with the boy in 1610. He met with the great scientists and intellectuals of the time in Paris at Place Royale. He learned from Descartes, Pascal, and Gassendi. He studies with Marin Mersenne the works of Galileo. Thomas Hobbes learned many things about science and philosophy before returning with the Earl back to England. One event that changed Hobbes’s life was when Hobbes read Euclid’s “Elements” in a library in Geneva. While reading the text, Thomas Hobbes came to believing that geometry was an ‘old science that hath pleased God to bestow on mankind’. This made him obsessed with geometry and convinced Hobbes that this subject was what would help him find the truth in the science of politics. The English Civil War had made another impact on Thomas Hobbes. After returning to England from his tour in 1637, Hobbes had seen many political pamphlets being given and had decided to work on a system of…

    • 1339 Words
    • 6 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    Locke Vs Rousseau

    • 1249 Words
    • 5 Pages

    Every society is set up to protect their people’s rights and liberty and make sure that everyone is equal. However, there are different approaches as to how a society should be set up to protect those rights and ensure equality throughout the society. John Locke and Jean Jacques Rousseau both offer different approaches to how a government should be assembled. Locke’s central belief, in Second Treatise of Government, is that society is set up to protect an individual’s private property right. People enter into a social contract where they give up particular rights to be protected by a common law and there is a common executive power that enforces said law. The common executive power that is set up within the society is there to ensure that…

    • 1249 Words
    • 5 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Better Essays

    Thomas Hobbes, Jean-Jacques Rousseau and Thomas Paine, three great political philosophers, all view the nature of man and society as anarchical, which is a state of lawlessness or political disorder due to the absence of governmental authority, making it “war of all against all”. The utopian society of individuals enjoys complete freedom without government, wherein there is a display of a lack of morality for most of the time.…

    • 1380 Words
    • 6 Pages
    Better Essays
  • Good Essays

    Locke Vs Hobbes Essay

    • 669 Words
    • 3 Pages

    The battle between Hobbes and Locke still continues today through their influence on governments and how they believed government should work. Hobbes believed in an absolute monarch where they were to demand obedience in order to maintain order. On the other hand, John Locke thought that a Democracy was a better form of government provided that they had the right information to make. This form of government allows the people to keep their natural rights rather than giving them up in exchange for protection by the monarch. As a result of their views on human nature and what form government should take, it is easy to see why Lockean government is more powerful than Hobbesian by looking at past governments in history as well as logically.…

    • 669 Words
    • 3 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    The seventeenth century in England was a time of many kings. Within a century, the reigns of five kings as well as a military dictator had run rampant over England’s government. Starting with James I, the English monarchy traversed to Charles I, Oliver Cromwell, Charles II, James II, and finally William III. With the ascensions of Cromwell and William III, drastic events changed the course of England’s history, as well as influencing two famous philosophical men. Thomas Hobbes, author of Leviathan, and John Locke, author of Second Treatise on Civil Government, drew on their experiences of England’s monarchical turmoil to conceive very different political theories. Both Thomas Hobbes and John Locke were prominent political philosophers in the…

    • 967 Words
    • 4 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    Thomas Hobbes Imperialism

    • 902 Words
    • 4 Pages

    To better comprehend the reasons behind the philosophers’ dissimilarity in ideology, it is rather helpful to make sense of the historical circumstances of these two men. Thomas Hobbes was born in England in 1588. He claims that his premature birth was the result of his mother going into labor early after she heard that the Spanish Armada was on its way to invade England. Regarding the event of his birth, Hobbes wrote in his autobiography, “My Native place I'm not asham'd to own; Th'ill Times, and Ills born with me, I bemoan: For Fame had rumour'd, that a Fleet at Sea, Wou'd cause our Nations Catastrophe; And hereupon it was my Mother Dear Did bring forth Twins at once, both Me, and Fear” (Hobbes Autobiography 2).…

    • 902 Words
    • 4 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    The Age of Enlightenment spanned from the Middle 18th century and on to the French Revolution. It is defined as the time when thinkers emerged believing in shedding the light of science and reason on the world in order to question traditional ideas and ways of society’s norms and established hierarchies. Many philosophers presented many theories and beliefs to form questions in the minds of people. These questions entertained elites and aristocrats to pass by the time. Eventually these thinking games evolved into more serious ideas emerged and began challenging those in power. Enlightenment thinkers created many concepts to question the status of the royals and gaining the fear of the upper class, afraid that it would lead to social chaos, and ultimately result…

    • 477 Words
    • 2 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    history

    • 615 Words
    • 3 Pages

    Thomas Hobbes was an ideologist. He was an English philosopher. Hobbes favored dictatorship. Hobbes disagreed with Locke. Hobbes believed Humans are born selfish.…

    • 615 Words
    • 3 Pages
    Good Essays